« previous section | next section » |
This subsection of the lecture is devoted to the presentation
of an indirect
method of checking the validity of formulas also called
"apagogic proofs". The idea consists in assuming the negation of
original claim, deducing from this that one of the assumptions
is a false or an absurd result, and then conclude that the
assumption must have been wrong. This
type of proving is sometimes named proving
by reduction to nonsense or proving by contradiction. The examples
presented
below are based on this
principle.
Example 6.5.1
Let' us consider the formula (( α ∧ β) → γ) → ( α → ( β → γ)), known as the law of exportation.We want to prove that this proposition is a tautology of the propositional calculus, i.e. irrespective of the valuation of the component propositions the whole expression has always value 1.
Assume that it is not true, i.e. there exists an interpretation v of α, β, γthat ((( α ∧ β ) → γ) → ( α → ( β → γ )))(v) = 0. Because the implication can take 0 value only in one case, therefore, it must be
According to the implication's property and (2) we obtain
It follows from (4) that ( β)(v) = 1 and ( γ)(v) = 0. Hence, with (3) we conclude ( α ∧ β)(v) = 1, and therefore (( α ∧ β) → γ)(v) = 0, what contradicts (1).
Thus, our starting assumption is not true, i.e. the formula ((( α ∧ β) → γ ) → ( α → ( β → γ)))(v) = 1 always holds. ♦
The scheme which was used in the example 6.5.1 is based on the fact that by the supposition of falsity of the proved proposition we conclude the property (1) and after a while we find out its contradiction. Because there is no interpretation in which it may be at the same time satisfied and non-satisfied, then the considered formula is a tautology, i.e. is valid for every valuation of its propositional variables.
A simplified version of our apagogic method of reasoning presented in the example 6.5.1 is shown on the figure 6.4.1. Each horizontal lines split next steps of the presented proof. As a result of the first four steps we obtain values of the formulas α, β and γ. These stages of reasoning can be characterised by the formula's deep-walk behaviour. In the fifth step we gather all obtained information and write it down into appropriate positions in the predecessor of the considered formula. Now, the reverse process starts: beginning with the simple formulas up to a complex one. This leads to the step 7, where we spot a contradiction of obtained information: the same vertical column stores simultaneously 0 as well as 1 value.
Fig 6.5.1 An example of application of apagogic proving
method.
Apagogic proofs are also presented in the following examples.
Example 6.5.2
If the function g : Y → X is the inverse of f: X → Y, then both f as well as g are one-to-one functions. We remember that the function g: Y → X is called an inverse to the function f : X → Y, iff Y = f(X) and X = g(Y) as well as g(f(x))=x for every x ∈ X.
We assume that f is not a different-value function. Let x1 ≠ x2 and f(x1)=f(x2). Because g is a function then for equal arguments it takes the same values, i.e. g(f(x1)) =g(f(x2)). Hence, according to the definition of a one-to-one function, we obtain x1= g(f(x1)) = g(f(x2)) = x2 which contradicts the previously established assumption that x1 ≠ x2.
If g is not a one-to-one function, then there are in the set Y two different elements y1, y2 such that g(y1) = g(y2). Then we obtain
(*) f (g(y1)) = f(g(y2)).
Because g is the inverse to f thus Y = f(X), i.e. y1, y2 ∈ f(X). It follows that there exist such elements x1, x2 in X, then f(x1) = y1 as well as f(x2) = y2. Putting it to the equation (*) we obtain
f(g(f(x1)) ) = f(g(f(x2)) ). Using a property of the inverse function we have f(x1) = f(x2) , and therefore y1=y2. Contradiction. Thus, if only y1 ≠ y2 then g(y1) ≠ g(y2). That's why g is also a one-to-one function. ♦
Example 6.5.3
Now we want to prove that √ 2 is
an irrational number. In order to do that we need to show that, if x2
= 2, then x cannot be a rational number. Let us assume the
opposite
According to (2) x = n/m for some arbitrary numbers n, m, where m ≠ 0. We may assume that n as well as m do not share common divisors other than 1 (in the opposite case it is enough to divide n and m by their greatest common divisor).
We obtain n2/m2 = 2, that is n2 = 2m2. It follows from here that n2 is an even number. As a consequence n must also be an even number (if n is odd, then for example n=2k+1 and n2= 4k2+ 4k+1 is also an odd number). Let n = 2k, then we obtain n2 = 4k2 = 2m2. Hence 2k2 = m2, i.e. m is an even number. Contradiction with the assumption that n as well as m do not have common divisors. Thus, √ 2 is an irrational number. ♦
The above-mentioned example of an apagogic proof is based on the idea of reduction to a contradiction.
The proofs that use of rules of transposition are also among apagogic proofs: instead of proving the implication ( α → β) we prove the proposition ( ¬ β → ¬ α).
Question 6.5.1 Prove that the formula ((( α
→ β) → α) → α) is a tautology
of propositional calculus. In order to do that, use the method of
reduction to a contradiction.
« previous section | next section » |